Search www.satyamag.com

Satya has ceased publication. This website is maintained for informational purposes only.

To learn more about the upcoming Special Edition of Satya and Call for Submissions, click here.

back issues

 

March 1997
Editorial: Dr. Frankenstein

By Martin Rowe

 

 

In 1976, Coca-Cola salesman John Moore went to the Medical Center of the University of California suffering from a rare disease called hairy-cell Leukemia. His doctor in this case, Dr. David Golde, recommended removing Moore's spleen. Moore agreed and his spleen was removed. Over the next seven years, John Moore returned to UC Medical Center, each time giving samples of blood, skin, bone marrow and sperm which he was told by Golde were needed to make sure he remained healthy.

During this period, Golde noticed that Moore's body was over-producing lymphokines, important components of the human immune system. Without consulting Moore, Golde began using samples from Moore's body to create a culture of cells which produced these lymphokines. Realizing that a lot of money could be made from this cell line, Golde and his research assistant Shirley Quan got a patent for the cell line and its derivatives and entered into commercial contracts with several companies and the University. When Moore found out about this, he took Golde to court so that he could financially benefit from the profits, which had totaled up to $350,000 a year in royalties. After failing in an initial trial, Moore appealed to the California Court of Appeal, which found that Moore was entitled to compensation. But, on further appeal, the Supreme Court of California found that Moore had no proprietary interest in his removed cells. It did say, however, that Golde had breached his fiduciary obligations by not telling Moore how he was using his cell-line.

The judgment of the Court, as related in detail in the absorbing and informative Body Parts: Property Rights and the Ownership of Human Biological Materials by E. Richard Gold, is essential to an understanding of biotechnology and its implications for human and non-human animal welfare and rights.

The majority of the Court felt that, while the human body is valuable in more than just how much it is worth to the market-and that Golde should have informed Moore of his commercial interests -žgranting Moore a property right for his own body would impede research. As the majority wrote: " 'companies [would be] unlikely to invest heavily in developing, manufacturing, or marketing a product when uncertainty about clear title exists.'ž"

Nevertheless, there was dissent among the judges. One opinion held that Moore's body was his own property, and that even though it was only tissue, Moore had a proprietary right prior to its "discovery" and should be able to benefit financially from its use. Another argued that other, non-economic values, such as dignity and equity, should be considered when debating the market value of human biological materials. Yet another opinion argued that property discourse and market value have no role when it comes to human biological materials. Not only did the market have no incentive to respect non-economic values, but the conclusion that a person willing to pay the most for something therefore is entitled to own that object simply did not reflect the multiformity of values humans place on their bodies.

The story of John Moore and his spleen offers clear indications of the patenting problems of biotechnology. The main judgments of courts in biotechnology cases have so far, as Gold relates, been based on assessments of how greatly the "discovery" concerned will impact the market. Courts have generally insisted that the greater good for society is contained solely in unfettered scientific research and development, and that courts should not stand in the way of what makes that possible -žthe investment of companies hoping for a dividend in a breakthrough drug. The courts have also argued, disingenuously to Gold, that other non-commercial concerns are beyond either their expertise or mandate. "It's up to Congress to legislate or debate the bigger issues," seems their common refrain.

While it is true that patent law is irreducibly connected to money, commerce and property, this still begs the question of whether biological materials should be patentable. Gold's book, ultimately to its limitation, sticks too closely to human biological materials. As animal advocates know, the link between human and non-human exploitation is merely a matter of degree rather than kind; and, as is clear from the history of patenting, the debate is not, and could not be, confined solely to human biological material. For 100 years before 1980, a wide variety of plant forms had been patented. That year, in a landmark case, a court allowed for the patenting of a moving living form, a bacterium that the court agreed could have commercial usage in oil spills. This precedent paved the way for the patenting by two Harvard researchers of a mouse with special cancer-producing properties known as the oncomouse. This in turn has encouraged the "development" of other animals: cows that produce more milk, pigs that provide leaner meat, and so on.

These developments, in tandem with the on-going, three billion-dollar Human Genome Project (an attempt to map all 100,000 genes on the human chromosome) and its corollary, the Human Genome Diversity Project (which is collecting hair, blood, and cell samples from 700 threatened indigenous communities), has left open not only the possibility of more John Moores, but-as has already occurred-the patenting of the genome of whole peoples. In 1993, when the Guaymi people of Panama discovered their cell line had been patented as part of the Diversity Project, they had to apply to then Secretary of Commerce Ron Brown and the World Trade Organization for control over their own cell line!

In the face of this extension of property discourse into all aspects of the organic world, it is easy to conclude that this is for greater goods and not the greater good. It is even harder to believe that, in spite of John Moore's success in the European courts or the revolt of consumers against genetically-altered plants in Europe and Asia, governmental agencies will rein in the super-dominant multinational organizations who stand to benefit from the global application of patent laws due to the passage of the General Agreement on Tariffs and Trade (GATT).

Now it could be argued that commercial traffic in human bodies-whether slavery or prostitution-forms the world's oldest and second oldest professions. Do not John Moore's attempts to get money from his body and the poor selling their organs to unscrupulous doctors represent only the exacerbation of human beings' ability to commodify themselves and others for short-term profit against their own best long-term interests? We've always done it, so how is this different?

First of all, of course, to contradict fatalists and tyrants everywhere, the fact that we have always done it doesn't make it right. Secondly, we should begin to insert into all property discourse the discourse of equity and justice and remove sentient living organisms from property discourse altogether. And thirdly, to accept the parameters of the above argument, what seems to be different is that this form of "bioprospecting" is now beyond individual control. Already scientists are combing the world and indigenous communities looking for miracle cures which are currently unpatented and which could make them billions of dollars as well as deny the dispossessed any possible remuneration. Moreover, as Stuart Newman in this issue of Satya suggests, the genetic manipulation of human embryos which are brought to term offers the prospect of an entire individual human being "owned"žby their patenter. If that seems far-fetched, then consider this final story. In 1988, Baylor University of Texas filed a European patent which included the genetic alteration of a human female who could eventually be used as a drug factory. An attorney representing Baylor indicated that the university wanted to get in the game quickly because "someone, somewhere may decide humans are patentable" and wanted to make sure they had rights on the production of any drugs which came out of the woman.

Dr. Frankenstein, I presume.


Body Parts: Property Rights and the Ownership of Human Biological Materials
by E. Richard Gold. Georgetown: Georgetown University Press (1996). 242 pages. $49.95 hbd.

 


© STEALTH TECHNOLOGIES INC.
All contents are copyrighted. Click here to learn about reprinting text or images that appear on this site.